language-icon Old Web
English
Sign In

Jus ad bellum

Jus ad bellum (Latin for 'right to war') is a set of criteria that are to be consulted before engaging in war in order to determine whether entering into war is permissible, that is, whether it is a just war. Jus ad bellum (Latin for 'right to war') is a set of criteria that are to be consulted before engaging in war in order to determine whether entering into war is permissible, that is, whether it is a just war. Jus ad bellum is sometimes considered a part of the laws of war, but the term 'laws of war' can also be considered to refer to jus in bello, which concerns whether a war is conducted justly (regardless of whether the initiation of hostilities was just). Jus ad bellum refers to 'legitimate reasons a State may engage in war.' These rules focus on certain criteria for what makes a war just. Article 51 of the UN Charter clarifies: 'Nothing in the present Charter shall impair the inherent right of individual or collective self-defense if an armed attack occurs against a Member of the United Nations.' An international agreement limiting the justifiable reasons for a country to declare war against another is concerned with jus ad bellum. In addition to bilateral non-aggression pacts, the twentieth century saw multilateral treaties defining entirely new restrictions against going to war. The three most notable examples are the Kellogg-Briand Pact outlawing war as an instrument of national policy, the London Charter (known also as the Nuremberg Charter) defining 'crimes against peace' as one of three major categories of international crime to be prosecuted after World War II, and the United Nations Charter, which binds nations to seek resolution of disputes by peaceful means and requires authorization by the United Nations before a nation may initiate any use of force against another, beyond the inherent right of self-defense against an armed attack. By contrast, agreements defining limits on acceptable conduct while already engaged in war are considered 'rules of war' and are referred to as the jus in bello. Thus, the Geneva Conventions are a set of 'jus in bello'. Doctrines concerning the protection of civilians in wartime, or the need for 'proportionality' when force is used, are addressed to issues of conduct within a war, but the same doctrines can also shed light on the question of when it is lawful (or unlawful) to go to war in the first place. The principle of right authority suggests that a war is just only if waged by a legitimate authority. Such authority is rooted in the notion of state sovereignty. In his Summa Theologica St. Thomas Aquinas notes that to be a just war, war has not only to be declared publicly, but also must be declared by the proper authority. Proper authority is what differentiates war from murder: 'It is the rules of warfare that give the practice meaning, that distinguish war from murder and soldiers from criminals'. A soldier is treated as a prisoner of war (POW) and not a criminal because they are operating under the proper authority of the state and cannot be held individually responsible for actions committed under the orders of their military leadership. According to the principle of right intention, the aim of war must not be to pursue narrowly defined national interests, but rather to re-establish a just peace. This state of peace should be preferable to the conditions that would have prevailed had the war not occurred. Wars cannot be fought simply to annex property or install a regime change. Current doctrines of 'anticipatory self-defense' or preemptive strikes, sometimes associated with the Bush Doctrine, have challenged concepts of right intention/just cause. Right cause includes humanitarian intervention, particularly when actions 'shock the conscience'. The responsibility to protect covers more in depth the nature of humanitarian intervention. According to this principle, there must be good grounds for concluding that aims of the just war are achievable. This principle emphasizes that mass violence must not be undertaken if it is unlikely to secure the just cause. This criterion is to avoid invasion for invasion's sake and links to the proportionality criteria. One cannot invade if there is no chance of actually winning. However, wars are fought with imperfect knowledge, so one must simply be able to make a logical case that one can win; there is no way to know this in advance. These criteria move the conversation from moral and theoretical grounds to practical grounds. Essentially, this is meant to gather coalition building and win approval of other state actors.

[ "Just war theory", "Use of force" ]
Parent Topic
Child Topic
    No Parent Topic