language-icon Old Web
English
Sign In

Aronszajn tree

In set theory, an Aronszajn tree is an uncountable tree with no uncountable branches and no uncountable levels. For example, every Suslin tree is an Aronszajn tree. More generally, for a cardinal κ, a κ-Aronszajn tree is a tree of height κ in which all levels have size less than κ and all branches have height less than κ (so Aronszajn trees are the same as ℵ 1 {displaystyle aleph _{1}} -Aronszajn trees). They are named for Nachman Aronszajn, who constructed an Aronszajn tree in 1934; his construction was described by Kurepa (1935). In set theory, an Aronszajn tree is an uncountable tree with no uncountable branches and no uncountable levels. For example, every Suslin tree is an Aronszajn tree. More generally, for a cardinal κ, a κ-Aronszajn tree is a tree of height κ in which all levels have size less than κ and all branches have height less than κ (so Aronszajn trees are the same as ℵ 1 {displaystyle aleph _{1}} -Aronszajn trees). They are named for Nachman Aronszajn, who constructed an Aronszajn tree in 1934; his construction was described by Kurepa (1935). A cardinal κ for which no κ-Aronszajn trees exist is said to have the tree property(sometimes the condition that κ is regular and uncountable is included). Kőnig's lemma states that ℵ 0 {displaystyle aleph _{0}} -Aronszajn trees do not exist. The existence of Aronszajn trees ( = ℵ 1 {displaystyle =aleph _{1}} -Aronszajn trees) was proven by Nachman Aronszajn, and implies that the analogue of Kőnig's lemma does not hold for uncountable trees. The existence of ℵ 2 {displaystyle aleph _{2}} -Aronszajn trees is undecidable (assuming a certain large cardinal axiom): more precisely, the continuum hypothesis implies the existence of an ℵ 2 {displaystyle aleph _{2}} -Aronszajn tree, and Mitchell and Silver showed that it is consistent (relative to the existence of a weakly compact cardinal) that no ℵ 2 {displaystyle aleph _{2}} -Aronszajn trees exist. Jensen proved that V = L implies that there is a κ-Aronszajn tree (in fact a κ-Suslin tree) for every infinite successor cardinal κ. Cummings & Foreman (1998) showed (using a large cardinal axiom) that it is consistent that no ℵ n {displaystyle aleph _{n}} -Aronszajn trees exist for any finite n other than 1. If κ is weakly compact then no κ-Aronszajn trees exist. Conversely if κ is inaccessible and no κ-Aronszajn trees exist then κ is weakly compact. An Aronszajn tree is called special if there is a function f from the tree to the rationals so thatf(x) < f(y) whenever x < y. Martin's axiom MA( ℵ 1 {displaystyle aleph _{1}} ) implies that all Aronszajn trees are special. The stronger proper forcing axiom implies the stronger statement that for any two Aronszajn trees there is a club set of levels such that the restrictions of the trees to this set of levels are isomorphic, which says that in some sense any two Aronszajn trees are essentially isomorphic (Abraham & Shelah 1985). On the other hand, it is consistent that non-special Aronszajn trees exist, and this is also consistent with the generalized continuum hypothesis plus Suslin's hypothesis (Schlindwein 1994).

[ "Combinatorics", "Discrete mathematics", "Topology", "Mathematical analysis" ]
Parent Topic
Child Topic
    No Parent Topic